Excerpts from Chapter IV (Isaiah Berlin and the Anti-totalitarians) from What Was Liberalism? by James Traub

Berlin’s field was political and moral philosophy, but he did not think of himself as a philosopher standing in the line of succession from Locke and Rousseau and Mill. Rather, he studied the ideas of those thinkers like an epidemiologist tracing the path of a disease back to the source. Berlin was, in short, a historian of ideas, or, as he came to think of himself, a historian of philosophy. He did not deliver a comprehensive statement of his own views until 1952, when he delivered a series of lectures on Enlightenment and Romantic thinkers…Berlin’s point: the heroic idealism of the Romantic era had offered a blueprint, and a banner, for modern tyrants.

…In the second lecture, on Rousseau…[Berlin] explained that, like a mathematician who has cut the knot of an ancient conundrum, Rousseau solved, or believed he had solved, the apparently intrinsic tension between liberty and authority, or legitimate power. Rousseau viewed both values as absolute: individual liberty was inalienable, but so, too, were the moral rules that govern right behavior and thus must govern society. Must one, then, continually adjust the dial between these two poles, as previous thinkers had supposed? Not at all. Both were absolute. However, Rousseau insisted, a rational man would never will for himself what was at variance with the “general will.” If he did, it was not his true, natural self speaking but the self corrupted by the artifice, the pervasive falseness, of society. In a just society, liberty and authority would be fully harmonized. By this strange turn of logic, Berlin went on, Rousseau, the champion of liberty who helped inspire the French Revolution, ended up betraying the idea of liberty — just as the Revolution itself did. Berlin was hardly the first thinker to lodge this allegation; so, too, had Constant. But Berlin demonstrated the link between the apparently noble principle of the general will and the slave ideology of Lenin and Stalin in a way that no listener in 1952 could have missed:

You want to give people unlimited liberty, because otherwise they cease to be men; and yet at the same time you want them to live according to the rules. If they can be made to love the rules, then they will want the rules, not so much because the rules are rules as because they love them…So Rousseau says, “Man is born free, and yet he is everywhere in chains.” What sort of chains?…If the chains are simply rules the very obedience to which is the most free, the strongest, the most spontaneous expression of your own inner nature, then the chains no longer bind you — since self-control is not control. Self-control is freedom.

In these lectures Berlin asked how liberty, the greatest of all political values, comes to be perverted into its opposite….The grain of totalitarianism is planted when we say that we can achieve all our goals through a single formula, that we can enjoy, as Rousseau insisted, absolute liberty even amidst absolute authority. Modern man, beset by agoraphobia, as Berlin put it, is drawn to the promise of an effortless resolution. The total system is beautiful and sleek, precisely because it is total. But of course it is false, for all good things do not, in fact, go together. We must choose among competing goods — so much liberty, so much equality, so much justice, and so on. There is no “right” choice; each of us will have different preferences. A liberal society does not tell us what we should wish but honors the variety of wishes. Mill remained a hero to Berlin throughout his life, in part because Mill understood the moral importance of variety — of pluralism. He defended the right of every individual to act and think according to his or her own particular and even peculiar nature. Because, Berlin wrote, Mill’s view of human nature accepts individuals’ “perpetual incompleteness, self-transformation and novelty, his words are today alive and relevant to our own problems.”

…One kind of liberty had been enough for John Stuart Mill, but in the twentieth century a new and, Berlin thought, insidious understanding of freedom had gained a powerful purchase in people’s minds. Today, Berlin said, an “open war” is being fought between “two systems of ideas” — liberalism and communism — founded on two very different understandings of what it means to be free.

Berlin began by observing that all classical liberal thinkers have understood liberty as freedom from coercion. He called this doctrine “negative liberty” because it defines the sphere within which no external obligation may be imposed on an individual. For Berlin, as for Mill, political thinking began with the autonomy, and thus the sanctity, of the person. Indeed, in his essay “John Stuart Mill and the Ends of Life,” Berlin observed that, despite Mill’s dutiful effort in On Liberty to provide a utilitarian justification for maximum individual freedom, he plainly regarded liberty as a good in itself. People have different tastes, wishes, ideas, temperaments; the great fact of human life is not uniformity but diversity. To deprive people of their freedom to speak and behave as they wish is to deny them the fullness of their individuality. Berlin…wrote that liberal thinkers naturally disagree on the scope and nature of Mill’s inviolable sphere of private thought and action, but the minimum must be understood as “that which a man cannot give up without offending against the essence of his human nature.”

But here Berlin made a striking observation: Mill, he said, has confused two different ideas. The idea of coercion is bad and liberty good is logically distinct from Mill’s belief that individuals in conditions of liberty will be able to fully realize their own gifts and that a society marked by a commitment to freedom will reach the greatest heights of which humans are capable. The “fiery individualism” Mill held out as an affirmative good often emerged from highly disciplined societies, like the Scottish Puritans, that routinely and intentionally infringed on the sphere of private speech and behavior. Negative liberty, in turn, may flourish in the absence of the kind of self-government that Mill thought of as the end point of a truly liberal society; one need only think of the despot who leaves his subjects alone so long as they obey. The liberal wish for private space and the accompanying vision of human and social self-realization are not only not the same thing, but they may conflict with one another. One, Berlin wrote, is “freedom from” — that is, freedom from coercion — while the other is “freedom to” — that is, to lead a certain kind of life. It is this freedom that Berlin described as “positive liberty.”

…The latter, [Berlin] wrote, springs from the classically liberal “wish on the part of the individual to be his own master.” What’s more, negative liberty, by itself, offers no guidance on how to shape a better life, not only for oneself but for one’s fellow man. Many liberals, Berlin observed, feel beleaguered and at times tormented by the conclusion that their liberty has been purchased at the cost of the suffering of others — through, for example, an unjust economic order. They, therefore, insist on the kinds of large-scale social changes that would lead to “equality of liberty.” [George] Orwell, for example, thought just this way. Berlin accepted that such principles may well constitute “the foundations of liberal morality.” But, he added, crucially, they should not be described as aspects of liberty. If you sacrifice some of your freedom, or society’s freedom, in the name of some other good, you may well have produced more fairness or justice or common decency, but you have diminished the stock of liberty.

This sounds very much like a linguistic quibble. Why is it so important to prevent the misuse of “liberty”?…Berlin’s answer is that totalitarianism has learned to speak the language of liberty, and one must distinguish between true and specious uses of this beguiling word…If one says, as Rousseau did, that, whatever you may think you want, your true self, your rational self, must want to live in accordance with this or that set of principles, then you must put aside your puny wishes. [Johann Gottlieb] Fichte took this dangerous claim one step further by insisting that the individual discovers the highest form of self-realization by submitting to the will of the group, itself the embodiment of true freedom. “Once I take this view,” Berlin concluded, “I am in a position to ignore the actual wishes of men or societies, to bully, oppress, torture them in the name, and on the behalf, of their ‘real’ selves.”

…[F]ascism and communism also posed a dire threat to something so elemental to society that political thinkers of earlier generations had barely needed to take account of it: the very idea of truth. In Darkness at Noon, the 1940 novel that exposed the reality of the Soviet show trials, Arthur Koestler furnished a terrifying picture of a society based on slogans universally understood to be grotesque lies. The struggle to vindicate liberal principles had to be waged not only on political or economic lines but on cognitive ones as well. This conviction lay at the core of Karl Popper’s idea that the “open society” depended above all on the preservation of the spirit of scientific inquiry.

The great prophet on the totalitarian assault on truth was, of course, George Orwell, who first came to recognize the danger during the Spanish Civil War, when he saw that the newspapers of all sides described events that bore no relation to reality. In an unpublished essay apparently written in 1942, he recalled having said to Koestler, “History stopped in 1936” — the year of the Soviet show trials. Thereafter one would never know what was true and what had been fabricated. The experience, Orwell wrote, had left him with the feeling that “the very concept of objective truth is fading out of the world.” This fear came more and more to preoccupy Orwell. In 1947 he wrote that because totalitarian regimes insist that the leadership is infallible, history must be perpetually rewritten in order to eliminate evidence of past mistakes. Totalitarianism thus “demands a disbelief in the very existence of objective truth.” Orwell added darkly that “to be corrupted by totalitarianism one does not have to live in a totalitarian country”; one simply had to surrender to certain habits of thought.

…Like Berlin, Popper looked to reason to counter the pull of the tribal, the magical, the extrahuman. Rationalism, Popper wrote, “is an attitude of readiness to listen to critical arguments and to learn from experience. It is fundamentally an attitude of admitting that ‘I may be wrong and you may be right, and by an effort, we may get nearer to the truth.'” The irrational certitudes of Hitler and Stalin, the incantatory logic that hypnotized whole populations, turned rational skepticism into the sword and shield of liberalism. In his 1947 essay “Philosophy and Politics,” the philosopher Bertrand Russell asserted that “the essence of the liberal outlook lies not in what opinions are held, but in how they are held: instead of being held dogmatically, they are held tentatively, and with a consciousness that new evidence may at any moment lead to their abandonment.”

The full book can be purchased here.

Excerpts from Chapter XVII (Science and Values) from The Scientific Outlook by Bertrand Russell

Science in its beginnings was due to men who were in love with the world. They perceived the beauty of the stars and the sea, of the winds and the mountains. Because they loved them their thoughts dwelt upon them, and they wished to understand them more intimately than a mere outward contemplation made possible. “The world,” said Heraclitus, “is an ever-living fire, with measures kindling and measures going out.” Heraclitus and the other Ionian philosophers, from whom came the first impulse to scientific knowledge, felt the strange beauty of the world almost like a madness in the blood. They were men of Titanic passionate intellect, and from the intensity of their intellectual passion the whole movement of the modern world has sprung.

…When I come to die I shall not feel that I have lived in vain. I have seen the earth turn red at evening, the dew sparkling in the morning, and the snow shining under a frosty sun; I have smelt rain after drought, and have heard the stormy Atlantic beat upon the granite shores of Cromwell.

…Knowing and feeling are equally essential ingredients both in the life of the individual and in that of the community. Knowledge, if it is wide and intimate, brings with it a realization of distant times and places, an awareness that the individual is not omnipotent or all-important, and a perspective in which values are seen more clearly than by those to whom a distant view is impossible. Even more important than knowledge is the life of the emotions. A world without delight and without affection is a world destitute of value.

The full book can be purchased here.

Excerpt from Chapter XI (Technique in Society) from The Scientific Outlook by Bertrand Russell

From the technique of advertising it seems to follow that in the great majority of mankind any proposition will win acceptance if it is reiterated in such a way as to remain in the memory. Most of the things that we believe, we believe because we have heard them affirmed; we do not remember where or why they were affirmed, and we are therefore unable to be critical even when the affirmation was made by a man whose income would be increased by its acceptance and was not backed by any evidence whatever. Advertisements tend, therefore, as the technique becomes perfected, to be less and less argumentative, and more and more merely striking. So long as an impression is made, the desired result is achieved.

The full book can be purchased here.

Excerpt from Chapter VI (Beginnings of Scientific Technique) of The Scientific Outlook by Bertrand Russell

“We are accustomed, in our own day, to protests against the empire of machinery and eloquent yearnings for a return to a simpler day. In all this there is nothing new. Lao-Tze, who preceded Confucius and lived (if he lived at all) in the sixth century B.C., is just as eloquent as Ruskin on the subject of the destruction of ancient beauty by modern mechanical inventions. Roads and bridges and boats filled him with horror because they were unnatural. He speaks of music as modern high-brows speak of the cinema. He finds the hurry of modern life fatal to the contemplative outlook. When he could bear it no longer he left China, and disappeared among the Western barbarians. He believed that men should live according to nature — a view which is continually recurring throughout the ages, though always with a different connotation. Rousseau also believed in the return to nature, but no longer objected to roads and bridges and boats. It was Courts and late hours and the sophisticated pleasures of the rich that roused his ire. The sort of man that seemed to him an unspoiled child of nature would have seemed to Lao-Tze incredibly different from those that he calls ‘the pure men of old.’ Lao-Tze objects to the taming of horses, and to the arts of the potter and carpenter; to Rousseau the carpenter would seem the very epitome of honest toil. ‘Return to nature’ means, in practice, return to those conditions to which the writer in question was accustomed in his youth. Return to nature, if it were taken seriously, would involve the death by starvation of some 90 per cent of the population of civilized countries. Industrialism as it exists at the present day undoubtedly has grave difficulties, but they are not to be cured by a return to the past, any more than were the difficulties from which China suffered in the time of Lao-Tze, or France in the time of Rousseau.

Science as knowledge advanced very rapidly throughout the whole of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, but it was not until near the end of the eighteenth century that it began to affect the technique of production. There was less change in methods of work from Ancient Egypt to 1750 than there has been from 1750 to the present day. Certain fundamental advances had been slowly acquired: speech, fire, writing, agriculture, the domestication of animals, the working of metals, gunpowder, printing, and the art of governing a large empire from a centre, though this last could not attain anything like its present perfection before the invention of the telegraph and steam locomotion. Each of these advances, because it came slowly, was fitted in, without too much difficulty, to the framework of traditional life, and men were at no point conscious of a revolution in their daily habits. Almost all the things that an adult man wished to speak about had been familiar to him as a child, and to his father and grandfather before him. This had, undoubtedly, certain good effects which have become lost through the rapid technical progress of modern times. The poet could speak of contemporary life in words that had become rich through long usage, and full of colour through the embedded emotions of past ages. Nowadays he must either ignore contemporary life or fill his poems with words that are stark and harsh. It is possible, in poetry, to write a letter, but difficult to speak over the telephone; it is possible to listen to Lydian airs, but not to the radio; it is possible to ride like the wind upon a fiery steed, but difficult, in any known metre, to go much faster than the wind in an automobile. The poem may wish for wings to fly to his love, but feels rather foolish in doing so when he remembers that he could order an aeroplane at Croydon.

…The most essential characteristic of scientific technique is that it proceeds from experiment, not from tradition. The experimental habit of mind is a difficult one for most people to maintain; indeed, the science of one generation has already become the tradition of the next, and there are still wide fields, notably that of religion, into which the experimental spirit has hardly penetrated at all. Nevertheless it is this spirit which is characteristic of modern times as contrasted with all earlier ages, and it is because of this spirit that the power of man in relation to his environment has become, during the last hundred and fifty years, so immeasurably greater than it was in the civilization of the past.”

The full book can be found here.

Excerpt from Chapter V (Science and Religion) from The Scientific Outlook by Bertrand Russell

“Are we to infer from [accepting the hypothesis that the world began at some definite, though unknown, date] that the world was made by a Creator? Certainly not, if we are to adhere to the canons of valid scientific inference. There is no reason whatever why the universe should not have begun spontaneously, except that it seems odd that it should do so; but there is no law of nature to the effect that things which seem odd to us must not happen. To infer a Creator is to infer a cause, and causal inferences are only admissible in science when they proceed from observed causal laws. Creation out of nothing is an occurrence which has not been observed. There is, therefore, no better reason to suppose that the world was caused by a Creator than to suppose that it was uncaused; either equally contradicts the causal laws that we can observe.

…The purely intellectual argument on this point may be put in a nutshell: is the Creator amenable to the laws of physics or is He not? If He is not, He cannot be inferred from physical phenomena, since no physical causal law can lead to Him; if He is, we shall have to apply the second law of thermodynamics to Him and suppose that He also had to be created at some remote period. But in that case He has lost His raison d’être.”

The full book can be found here.

Excerpt from Part I, Chapter II (Characteristics of Scientific Method) from The Scientific Outlook by Bertrand Russell

“When a man tells you that he knows the exact truth about anything, you are safe in inferring that he is an inexact man. Every careful measurement in science is always given with the probable error, which is a technical term, conveying a precise meaning. It means: that amount of error which is just as likely to be greater than the actual error as to be less. It is characteristic of those matters in which something is known with exceptional accuracy that, in them, every observer admits that he is likely to be wrong, and knows about how much wrong he is likely to be. In matters where the truth is not ascertainable, no one admits that there is the slightest possibility of even the minutest error in his opinions. Who ever heard of a theologian prefacing his creed, or a politician concluding his speeches, with a statement as to the probable error in his opinions? It is an odd fact that subjective certainty is inversely proportional to objective certainty. The less reason a man has to suppose himself in the right, the more vehemently he asserts that there is no doubt whatever that he is exactly right. It is a practice of theologians to laugh at science because it changes. ‘Look at us,’ they say. ‘What we asserted at the Council of Nicea we still assert; whereas what the scientists asserted only two or three years ago is already forgotten and antiquated.’ Men who speak in this way have not grasped the great idea of successive approximations. No man who has the scientific temper asserts that what is now believed in science is exactly right; he asserts that it is a stage on the road towards the exact truth. When a change occurs in science, as, for example, from Newton’s law of gravitation to Einstein’s, what had been done is not overthrown, but is replaced by something slightly more accurate. Suppose you measured yourself with a rough apparatus, and came to the conclusion that you were 6ft. tall: you would not suppose, if you were wise, that your height was exactly 6 ft., but rather that your height was (say) between 5 ft. 11 in. and 6 ft. 1 in.; and if a very careful measurement showed that your height was (within a tenth of an inch) 5 ft. 11 9/10 in. you would not consider that that had overthrown the previous result. The previous result was that your height was about six feet , and this remains true. The case with the changes in science is precisely analogous.”

The full book can be found here.

Excerpt from Part I, Chapter I (Examples of Scientific Method: Galileo) from The Scientific Outlook by Bertrand Russell

“Scientific method, simple as it is in essence, has been acquired only with great difficulty, and is still employed only by a minority, who themselves confine its employment to a minority of the questions upon which they have opinions. If you number among your acquaintances some eminent man of science, accustomed to the minutest quantitative precision in his experiments and the most abstruse skill in his inference from them, you will be able to make him the subject of a little experiment which is likely to be by no means unilluminating. If you tackle him on party politics, theology, income tax, house-agents, the bumptiousness of the working-classes and other topics of a like nature, you are pretty sure, before long, to provoke an explosion, and to hear him expressing wholly untested opinions with a dogmatism which he would never display in regard to the well-founded results of his laboratory experiments.

As this illustration shows, the scientific attitude is in some degree unnatural to man; the majority of our opinions are wish-fulfilments, like dreams in the Freudian theory. The mind of the most rational among us may be compared to a stormy ocean of passionate convictions based upon desire, upon which float perilously a few tiny boats carrying a cargo of scientifically tested beliefs.

…It is not, however, the lapses of scientific men that concern us when we are trying to describe [the] scientific method. A scientific opinion is one which there is some reason to believe true; an unscientific opinion is one which is held for some reason other than its probable truth.

…[Galileo’s] predecessors had known how the world was created, what was man’s destiny, the deepest mysteries of metaphysics, and the hidden principles governing the behaviour of bodies. Throughout the moral and material universe nothing was mysterious to them, nothing hidden, nothing incapable of exposition in orderly syllogism. Compared with all this wealth, what was left to the followers of Galileo? – a law of falling bodies, the theory of the pendulum, and Kepler’s ellipses. Can it be wondered at that the learned cried out at such a destruction of their hard-won wealth? As the rising sun scatters the multitude of stars, so Galileo’s few proved truths banished the scintillating firmament of medieval certainties.

Socrates had said that he was wiser than his contemporaries because he alone knew that he knew nothing. This was a rhetorical device. Galileo could have said with truth that he knew something, but knew he knew little, while his Aristotelian contemporaries knew nothing, but thought they knew much. Knowledge, as opposed to fantasies of wish-fulfillment, is difficult to come by. A little contact with real knowledge makes fantasies less acceptable.”

The full book can be found here.

An Outline of Intellectual Rubbish by Bertrand Russell

20200501_140314

The full essay is here.